CHAPTER I MUTUAL AID AMONG ANIMALS
Struggle for existence. Mutual Aid a law of
Nature and chief factor of progressive evolution. Invertebrates.
Ants and Bees. Birds, hunting and fishing associations.
Sociability. Mutual protection among small birds. Cranes, parrots.
The conception of struggle for existence as a factor of
evolution, introduced into science by Darwin and Wallace, has
permitted us to embrace an immensely wide range of phenomena in one
single generalization, which soon became the very basis of our
philosophical, biological, and sociological speculations. An
immense variety of facts:—adaptations of function and structure of
organic beings to their surroundings; physiological and anatomical
evolution; intellectual progress, and moral development itself,
which we formerly used to explain by so many different causes, were
embodied by Darwin in one general conception. We understood them as
continued endeavours—as a struggle against adverse
circumstances—for such a development of individuals, races, species
and societies, as would result in the greatest possible fulness,
variety, and intensity of life. It may be that at the outset Darwin
himself was not fully aware of the generality of the factor which
he first invoked for explaining one series only of facts relative
to the accumulation of individual variations in incipient species.
But he foresaw that the term which he was introducing into science
would lose its philosophical and its only true meaning if it were
to be used in its narrow sense only—that of a struggle between
separate individuals for the sheer means of existence. And at the
very beginning of his memorable work he insisted upon the term
being taken in its "large and metaphorical sense including
dependence of one being on another, and including (which is more
important) not only the life of the individual, but success in
leaving progeny."(1)
While he himself was chiefly using the term in its narrow
sense for his own special purpose, he warned his followers against
committing the error (which he seems once to have committed
himself) of overrating its narrow meaning. In The Descent of Man he
gave some powerful pages to illustrate its proper, wide sense. He
pointed out how, in numberless animal societies, the struggle
between separate individuals for the means of existence disappears,
how struggle is replaced by co-operation, and how that substitution
results in the development of intellectual and moral faculties
which secure to the species the best conditions for survival. He
intimated that in such cases the fittest are not the physically
strongest, nor the cunningest, but those who learn to combine so as
mutually to support each other, strong and weak alike, for the
welfare of the community. "Those communities," he wrote, "which
included the greatest number of the most sympathetic members would
flourish best, and rear the greatest number of offspring" (2nd
edit., p. 163). The term, which originated from the narrow
Malthusian conception of competition between each and all, thus
lost its narrowness in the mind of one who knew Nature.
Unhappily, these remarks, which might have become the basis
of most fruitful researches, were overshadowed by the masses of
facts gathered for the purpose of illustrating the consequences of
a real competition for life. Besides, Darwin never attempted to
submit to a closer investigation the relative importance of the two
aspects under which the struggle for existence appears in the
animal world, and he never wrote the work he proposed to write upon
the natural checks to over-multiplication, although that work would
have been the crucial test for appreciating the real purport of
individual struggle. Nay, on the very pages just mentioned, amidst
data disproving the narrow Malthusian conception of struggle, the
old Malthusian leaven reappeared—namely, in Darwin's remarks as to
the alleged inconveniences of maintaining the "weak in mind and
body" in our civilized societies (ch. v). As if thousands of
weak-bodied and infirm poets, scientists, inventors, and reformers,
together with other thousands of so-called "fools" and "weak-minded
enthusiasts," were not the most precious weapons used by humanity
in its struggle for existence by intellectual and moral arms, which
Darwin himself emphasized in those same chapters of Descent of Man.
It happened with Darwin's theory as it always happens with
theories having any bearing upon human relations. Instead of
widening it according to his own hints, his followers narrowed it
still more. And while Herbert Spencer, starting on independent but
closely allied lines, attempted to widen the inquiry into that
great question, "Who are the fittest?" especially in the appendix
to the third edition of the Data of Ethics, the numberless
followers of Darwin reduced the notion of struggle for existence to
its narrowest limits. They came to conceive the animal world as a
world of perpetual struggle among half-starved individuals,
thirsting for one another's blood. They made modern literature
resound with the war-cry of woe to the vanquished, as if it were
the last word of modern biology. They raised the "pitiless"
struggle for personal advantages to the height of a biological
principle which man must submit to as well, under the menace of
otherwise succumbing in a world based upon mutual extermination.
Leaving aside the economists who know of natural science but a few
words borrowed from second-hand vulgarizers, we must recognize that
even the most authorized exponents of Darwin's views did their best
to maintain those false ideas. In fact, if we take Huxley, who
certainly is considered as one of the ablest exponents of the
theory of evolution, were we not taught by him, in a paper on the
'Struggle for Existence and its Bearing upon Man,' that,
"from the point of view of the moralist, the animal world is
on about the same level as a gladiators' show. The creatures are
fairly well treated, and set to, fight hereby the strongest, the
swiftest, and the cunningest live to fight another day. The
spectator has no need to turn his thumb down, as no quarter is
given."
Or, further down in the same article, did he not tell us
that, as among animals, so among primitive men,
"the weakest and stupidest went to the wall, while the
toughest and shrewdest, those who were best fitted to cope with
their circumstances, but not the best in another way, survived.
Life was a continuous free fight, and beyond the limited and
temporary relations of the family, the Hobbesian war of each
against all was the normal state of existence."(2)
In how far this view of nature is supported by fact, will be
seen from the evidence which will be here submitted to the reader
as regards the animal world, and as regards primitive man. But it
may be remarked at once that Huxley's view of nature had as little
claim to be taken as a scientific deduction as the opposite view of
Rousseau, who saw in nature but love, peace, and harmony destroyed
by the accession of man. In fact, the first walk in the forest, the
first observation upon any animal society, or even the perusal of
any serious work dealing with animal life (D'Orbigny's, Audubon's,
Le Vaillant's, no matter which), cannot but set the naturalist
thinking about the part taken by social life in the life of
animals, and prevent him from seeing in Nature nothing but a field
of slaughter, just as this would prevent him from seeing in Nature
nothing but harmony and peace. Rousseau had committed the error of
excluding the beak-and-claw fight from his thoughts; and Huxley
committed the opposite error; but neither Rousseau's optimism nor
Huxley's pessimism can be accepted as an impartial interpretation
of nature.
As soon as we study animals—not in laboratories and museums
only, but in the forest and the prairie, in the steppe and the
mountains—we at once perceive that though there is an immense
amount of warfare and extermination going on amidst various
species, and especially amidst various classes of animals, there
is, at the same time, as much, or perhaps even more, of mutual
support, mutual aid, and mutual defence amidst animals belonging to
the same species or, at least, to the same society. Sociability is
as much a law of nature as mutual struggle. Of course it would be
extremely difficult to estimate, however roughly, the relative
numerical importance of both these series of facts. But if we
resort to an indirect test, and ask Nature: "Who are the fittest:
those who are continually at war with each other, or those who
support one another?" we at once see that those animals which
acquire habits of mutual aid are undoubtedly the fittest. They have
more chances to survive, and they attain, in their respective
classes, the highest development of intelligence and bodily
organization. If the numberless facts which can be brought forward
to support this view are taken into account, we may safely say that
mutual aid is as much a law of animal life as mutual struggle, but
that, as a factor of evolution, it most probably has a far greater
importance, inasmuch as it favours the development of such habits
and characters as insure the maintenance and further development of
the species, together with the greatest amount of welfare and
enjoyment of life for the individual, with the least waste of
energy.
Of the scientific followers of Darwin, the first, as far as I
know, who understood the full purport of Mutual Aid as a law of
Nature and the chief factor of evolution, was a well-known Russian
zoologist, the late Dean of the St. Petersburg University,
Professor Kessler. He developed his ideas in an address which he
delivered in January 1880, a few months before his death, at a
Congress of Russian naturalists; but, like so many good things
published in the Russian tongue only, that remarkable address
remains almost entirely unknown.(3)
"As a zoologist of old standing," he felt bound to protest
against the abuse of a term—the struggle for existence—borrowed
from zoology, or, at least, against overrating its importance.
Zoology, he said, and those sciences which deal with man,
continually insist upon what they call the pitiless law of struggle
for existence. But they forget the existence of another law which
may be described as the law of mutual aid, which law, at least for
the animals, is far more essential than the former. He pointed out
how the need of leaving progeny necessarily brings animals
together, and, "the more the individuals keep together, the more
they mutually support each other, and the more are the chances of
the species for surviving, as well as for making further progress
in its intellectual development." "All classes of animals," he
continued, "and especially the higher ones, practise mutual aid,"
and he illustrated his idea by examples borrowed from the life of
the burying beetles and the social life of birds and some mammalia.
The examples were few, as might have been expected in a short
opening address, but the chief points were clearly stated; and,
after mentioning that in the evolution of mankind mutual aid played
a still more prominent part, Professor Kessler concluded as
follows:—
"I obviously do not deny the struggle for existence, but I
maintain that the progressive development of the animal kingdom,
and especially of mankind, is favoured much more by mutual support
than by mutual struggle…. All organic beings have two essential
needs: that of nutrition, and that of propagating the species. The
former brings them to a struggle and to mutual extermination, while
the needs of maintaining the species bring them to approach one
another and to support one another. But I am inclined to think that
in the evolution of the organic world—in the progressive
modification of organic beings—mutual support among individuals
plays a much more important part than their mutual struggle."(4)
The correctness of the above views struck most of the Russian
zoologists present, and Syevertsoff, whose work is well known to
ornithologists and geographers, supported them and illustrated them
by a few more examples. He mentioned sone of the species of falcons
which have "an almost ideal organization for robbery," and
nevertheless are in decay, while other species of falcons, which
practise mutual help, do thrive. "Take, on the other side, a
sociable bird, the duck," he said; "it is poorly organized on the
whole, but it practises mutual support, and it almost invades the
earth, as may be judged from its numberless varieties and species."
The readiness of the Russian zoologists to accept Kessler's
views seems quite natural, because nearly all of them have had
opportunities of studying the animal world in the wide uninhabited
regions of Northern Asia and East Russia; and it is impossible to
study like regions without being brought to the same ideas. I
recollect myself the impression produced upon me by the animal
world of Siberia when I explored the Vitim regions in the company
of so accomplished a zoologist as my friend Polyakoff was. We both
were under the fresh impression of the Origin of Species, but we
vainly looked for the keen competition between animals of the same
species which the reading of Darwin's work had prepared us to
expect, even after taking into account the remarks of the third
chapter (p. 54). We saw plenty of adaptations for struggling, very
often in common, against the adverse circumstances of climate, or
against various enemies, and Polyakoff wrote many a good page upon
the mutual dependency of carnivores, ruminants, and rodents in
their geographical distribution; we witnessed numbers of facts of
mutual support, especially during the migrations of birds and
ruminants; but even in the Amur and Usuri regions, where animal
life swarms in abundance, facts of real competition and struggle
between higher animals of the same species came very seldom under
my notice, though I eagerly searched for them. The same impression
appears in the works of most Russian zoologists, and it probably
explains why Kessler's ideas were so welcomed by the Russian
Darwinists, whilst like ideas are not in vogue amidst the followers
of Darwin in Western Europe.
The first thing which strikes us as soon as we begin studying
the struggle for existence under both its aspects—direct and
metaphorical—is the abundance of facts of mutual aid, not only for
rearing progeny, as recognized by most evolutionists, but also for
the safety of the individual, and for providing it with the
necessary food. With many large divisions of the animal kingdom
mutual aid is the rule. Mutual aid is met with even amidst the
lowest animals, and we must be prepared to learn some day, from the
students of microscopical pond-life, facts of unconscious mutual
support, even from the life of micro-organisms. Of course, our
knowledge of the life of the invertebrates, save the termites, the
ants, and the bees, is extremely limited; and yet, even as regards
the lower animals, we may glean a few facts of well-ascertained
cooperation. The numberless associations of locusts, vanessae,
cicindelae, cicadae, and so on, are practically quite unexplored;
but the very fact of their existence indicates that they must be
composed on about the same principles as the temporary associations
of ants or bees for purposes of migration. As to the beetles, we
have quite well-observed facts of mutual help amidst the burying
beetles (Necrophorus). They must have some decaying organic matter
to lay their eggs in, and thus to provide their larvae with food;
but that matter must not decay very rapidly. So they are wont to
bury in the ground the corpses of all kinds of small animals which
they occasionally find in their rambles. As a rule, they live an
isolated life, but when one of them has discovered the corpse of a
mouse or of a bird, which it hardly could manage to bury itself, it
calls four, six, or ten other beetles to perform the operation with
united efforts; if necessary, they transport the corpse to a
suitable soft ground; and they bury it in a very considerate way,
without quarrelling as to which of them will enjoy the privilege of
laying its eggs in the buried corpse. And when Gleditsch attached a
dead bird to a cross made out of two sticks, or suspended a toad to
a stick planted in the soil, the little beetles would in the same
friendly way combine their intelligences to overcome the artifice
of Man. The same combination of efforts has been noticed among the
dung-beetles.
Even among animals standing at a somewhat lower stage of
organization we may find like examples. Some land-crabs of the West
Indies and North America combine in large swarms in order to travel
to the sea and to deposit therein their spawn; and each such
migration implies concert, co-operation, and mutual support. As to
the big Molucca crab (Limulus), I was struck (in 1882, at the
Brighton Aquarium) with the extent of mutual assistance which these
clumsy animals are capable of bestowing upon a comrade in case of
need. One of them had fallen upon its back in a corner of the tank,
and its heavy saucepan-like carapace prevented it from returning to
its natural position, the more so as there was in the corner an
iron bar which rendered the task still more difficult. Its comrades
came to the rescue, and for one hour's time I watched how they
endeavoured to help their fellow-prisoner. They came two at once,
pushed their friend from beneath, and after strenuous efforts
succeeded in lifting it upright; but then the iron bar would
prevent them from achieving the work of rescue, and the crab would
again heavily fall upon its back. After many attempts, one of the
helpers would go in the depth of the tank and bring two other
crabs, which would begin with fresh forces the same pushing and
lifting of their helpless comrade. We stayed in the Aquarium for
more than two hours, and, when leaving, we again came to cast a
glance upon the tank: the work of rescue still continued! Since I
saw that, I cannot refuse credit to the observation quoted by Dr.
Erasmus Darwin—namely, that "the common crab during the moulting
season stations as sentinel an unmoulted or hard-shelled individual
to prevent marine enemies from injuring moulted individuals in
their unprotected state."(5)
Facts illustrating mutual aid amidst the termites, the ants,
and the bees are so well known to the general reader, especially
through the works of Romanes, L. Buchner, and Sir John Lubbock,
that I may limit my remarks to a very few hints.(6) If we take an
ants' nest, we not only see that every description of work-rearing
of progeny, foraging, building, rearing of aphides, and so on—is
performed according to the principles of voluntary mutual aid; we
must also recognize, with Forel, that the chief, the fundamental
feature of the life of many species of ants is the fact and the
obligation for every ant of sharing its food, already swallowed and
partly digested, with every member of the community which may apply
for it. Two ants belonging to two different species or to two
hostile nests, when they occasionally meet together, will avoid
each other. But two ants belonging to the same nest or to the same
colony of nests will approach each other, exchange a few movements
with the antennae, and "if one of them is hungry or thirsty, and
especially if the other has its crop full … it immediately asks for
food." The individual thus requested never refuses; it sets apart
its mandibles, takes a proper position, and regurgitates a drop of
transparent fluid which is licked up by the hungry ant.
Regurgitating food for other ants is so prominent a feature in the
life of ants (at liberty), and it so constantly recurs both for
feeding hungry comrades and for feeding larvae, that Forel
considers the digestive tube of the ants as consisting of two
different parts, one of which, the posterior, is for the special
use of the individual, and the other, the anterior part, is chiefly
for the use of the community. If an ant which has its crop full has
been selfish enough to refuse feeding a comrade, it will be treated
as an enemy, or even worse. If the refusal has been made while its
kinsfolk were fighting with some other species, they will fall back
upon the greedy individual with greater vehemence than even upon
the enemies themselves. And if an ant has not refused to feed
another ant belonging to an enemy species, it will be treated by
the kinsfolk of the latter as a friend. All this is confirmed by
most accurate observation and decisive experiments.(7)
In that immense division of the animal kingdom which embodies
more than one thousand species, and is so numerous that the
Brazilians pretend that Brazil belongs to the ants, not to men,
competition amidst the members of the same nest, or the colony of
nests, does not exist. However terrible the wars between different
species, and whatever the atrocities committed at war-time, mutual
aid within the community, self-devotion grown into a habit, and
very often self-sacrifice for the common welfare, are the rule. The
ants and termites have renounced the "Hobbesian war," and they are
the better for it. Their wonderful nests, their buildings, superior
in relative size to those of man; their paved roads and overground
vaulted galleries; their spacious halls and granaries; their
corn-fields, harvesting and "malting" of grain;(8) their, rational
methods of nursing their eggs and larvae, and of building special
nests for rearing the aphides whom Linnaeus so picturesquely
described as "the cows of the ants"; and, finally, their courage,
pluck, and, superior intelligence—all these are the natural outcome
of the mutual aid which they practise at every stage of their busy
and laborious lives. That mode of life also necessarily resulted in
the development of another essential feature of the life of ants:
the immense development of individual initiative which, in its
turn, evidently led to the development of that high and varied
intelligence which cannot but strike the human observer.(9)