cover

Contents

Cover

About the Author

Also by John D. Barrow

Dedication

Title Page

Epigraph

Preface

1. Before the Beginning

Sameliness

2. Journey Towards Ultimate Reality

Mission to Mars

Measure for measure – parochial standards

Maintaining universal standards

A brilliant idea!

Max Planck’s natural units

Planck gets real

About time

3. Superhuman Standards

Einstein on constants

The deeper significance of Stoney-Planck units: the new Mappa Mundi

Otherworldliness

The super-Copernican Principle

4. Further, Deeper, Fewer: The Quest for a Theory of Everything

Numbers you can count on

Cosmic Cubism

New constants involve new labour

Numerology

5. Eddington’s Unfinished Symphony

Counting to 15,747,724,136,275,002,577,605,653,961,181,555,468,044, 717,914,527,116,709,366,231,425,076,185,631,031,296

Fundamentalism

Theatrical physics

6. The Mystery of the Very Large Numbers

Spooky numbers

A bold hypothesis

Of things to come at large

Big and old, dark and cold

The biggest number of all

7. Biology and the Stars

Is the universe old?

The chance of a lifetime

Other types of life

Prepare to meet thy doom

From coincidence to consequence

Life in an Edwardian universe

8. The Anthropic Principle

Anthropic arguments

A delicate balance

Brandon Carter’s principles

A close-run thing?

Some other anthropic principles

9. Altering Constants and Rewriting History

Rigid worlds versus flexi worlds

Inflationary universes

Virtual history – a little digression

10. New Dimensions

Living in a hundred dimensions

Walking with planisaurs

Polygons and polygamy

Why is life so easy for physicists?

The sad case of Paul Ehrenfest

The special case of Gerald Whitrow

The strange case of Theodor Kaluza and Oskar Klein

Varying constants on the brane

11. Variations on a Constant Theme

A prehistoric nuclear reactor

Alexander Shlyakhter’s insight

The Clock of Ages

Underground speculations

12. Reach for the Sky

Plenty of time

Inconstancy among the constants?

What do we make of that?

Our place in history

13. Other Worlds and Big Questions

Multiverses

The Great Universal Catalogue

Worlds without end

Journey’s end

Notes

Index

Copyright

About the Author

John D. Barrow is Research Professor of Mathematical Sciences in the Department of Applied Mathematics and Theoretical Physics at the University of Cambridge. He has recently been appointed the Gresham Professorship in Astronomy, one of the oldest and most esteemed professorships in science in the UK. He is the author of several bestselling books, including Theories of Everything, Impossibility and The Book of Nothing.

Also by John D. Barrow

Theories of Everything

The Left Hand of Creation

(With Joseph Silk)

L’Homme et le Cosmos

(With Frank J. Tipler)

The Anthropic Cosmological Principle

(with Frank J. Tipler)

The World Within the World

The Artful Universe

Pi in the Sky

Perché il mondo è matematico?

Impossibility

The Origin of the Universe

Between Inner Space and Outer Space

The Universe that Discovered Itself

The Book of Nothing

To Carol

logo

 

‘Not the power to remember, but its very opposite, the power to forget is a necessary condition for our existence.’

Sholem Ash

Preface

Some things never change. And this is a book about those things. Long ago, the happenings that made it into histories were the irregularities of experience: the unexpected, the catastrophic, and the ominous. Gradually, scientists came to appreciate the mystery of the regularity and predictability of the world. Despite the concatenation of chaotically unpredictable movements of atoms and molecules, our experience is of a world that possesses a deep-laid consistency and continuity. Our search for the source of that consistency looked first to the ‘laws’ of Nature that govern how things change. But gradually we have identified a collection of mysterious numbers which lie at the root of the consistency of experience. These are the constants of Nature. They give the Universe its distinctive character and distinguish it from others we might imagine. They capture at once our greatest knowledge and our greatest ignorance about the Universe. For, while we measure them to ever greater precision, fashion our fundamental standards of mass and time around their invariance, we cannot explain their values. We have never explained the numerical value of any of the constants of Nature. We have discovered new ones, linked old ones, and understood their crucial role in making things the way they are, but the reason for their values remain a deeply hidden secret. To search it out we will need to unpick the most fundamental theory of the laws of Nature, to discover if the constants that define them are fixed and framed by some over-arching logical consistency or whether chance still has a role to play.

Our first glimpses reveal a very peculiar situation. While some constants seem as if they will be fixed, others have the scope to be other than they are, and some seem completely untouched by everything else about the Universe. Do their values fall out at random? Could they really be different? How different could they be if life is to be possible in the Universe?

Back in 1986, my first book, The Anthropic Cosmological Principle, explored all the then-known ways in which life in the universe was sensitive to the values of the constants of Nature. Universes with slightly altered constants would be still-born, devoid of the potential to evolve and sustain the sort of organised complexity that we call life. Since that time, cosmologists have found more and more ways in which the Universe could exhibit variations in its defining constants; more and more ways in which life could have failed to emerge in the Universe. They have also begun to take seriously the possibility and actuality of other universes in which the constants of Nature do take different values. Inevitably, we find ourselves in a world where things fell out right. But what was the chance of that happening? Here we shall look at many of these possibilities, connecting them to the curious history of our attempts to understand the values of our constants of Nature.

Recently, one big story about the constants of Nature has produced a focus for media attention and detailed scientific research. It raises the most basic question of all: are the constants of Nature really constant after all? A new method of scrutinizing the constants of Nature over the last II billion years of the Universe’s history has been devised by a group of us. By looking at the atomic patterns barcoded into the light that reaches us from distant quasars we can look and see what atoms were like when the light began its journey billions of years ago. So, were the constants of Nature always the same? The answer, unexpected and shocking, raises new possibilities for the Universe and the laws that govern it. This book will tell you about them.

I would like to thank Bernard Carr, Rob Crittenden, Paul Davies, Michael Drinkwater, Chris Churchill, Freeman Dyson, Vladimir Dzuba, Victor Flambaum, Yasunori Fujii, Gary Gibbons, J. Richard Gott, Jörg Hensgen, Janna Levin, João Magueijo, Carlos Martins, David Mota, Michael Murphy, Jason Prochaska, Martin Rees, Håvard Sandvik, Wallace Sargent, Ilya Shlyakhter, Will Sulkin, Max Tegmark, Virginia Trimble, Neil Turok, John Webb, and Art Wolfe for discussions and contributions of ideas, results, and images.

I would also like to thank Elizabeth, for surviving at one stage the thought that the book might need to be retitled A River Runs Through It, and our three children David, Roger and Louise who were always worried that pocket-money might be a constant of Nature.

J.D.B

Cambridge, April 2002

chapter one

Before the Beginning

‘What happens first is not necessarily the beginning.’

Henning Mankell1

SAMELINESS

‘There is nothing that God hath established in a constant cause of nature, and which therefore is done everyday, but would seem a miracle, and exercise our admiration, if it were done but once.’

John Donne2

CHANGE IS A challenge. We live in the fastest moving period of human history. The world around us is driven by forces that make our lives increasingly sensitive to small changes and sudden responses. The elaboration of the Internet and the tentacles of the Worldwide Web have put us in instantaneous contact with computers and their owners all round the world. The threats from unchecked industrial progress have brought about ecological damage and environmental change that appears to be happening faster than even the gloomiest prophets of doom had predicted. Children seem to grow up faster. Political systems realign in new and unexpected ways more quickly and more often than ever before. Even human beings and the information they embody are facing editorial intervention by more ambitious spare-part surgery or the reprogramming of parts of our genetic code. Most forms of progress are accelerating and more and more parts of our experience have become entwined in the surge to explore all that is possible.

In the world of scientific exploration the recognition of the impact of change is not so new. By the end of the nineteenth century it had been appreciated that once upon a time the Earth and our solar system had not existed; that the human species must have changed in appearance and average mental capability over huge spans of time; and that in some broad and general way the Universe should be winding down, becoming a less hospitable and ordered place. During the twentieth century we have fleshed out this skeletal picture of a changing Universe. The climate and topography of our planet is continually changing and so are the species that live upon it. Most dramatically of all, we have discovered that the entire universe of stars and galaxies is in a state of dynamic change, with great clusters of galaxies flying away from one another into a future that will be very different from the present. We have begun to appreciate that we are living on borrowed time. Cataclysmic astronomical events are common; worlds collide. Planet Earth has been hit in the past by comets and asteroids. One day its luck will run out, the shield provided so fortuitously by the vast planet Jupiter, guarding the outer reaches of our solar system, will not be able to save us. Eventually, even our Sun will die. Our Milky Way galaxy will be drawn into a vast black hole deep in its centre. Life like our own will end. Survivors will need to have changed their form, their homes and their nature to such an extent that we would be challenged to call their continued existence ‘living’ by our own standards today.

We have recognised the simple secrets of chaos and unpredictability which beset so many parts of the world around us. We understand our changing weather but we cannot predict it. We have appreciated the similarities between complexities like this and those that emerge from systems of human interaction – societies, economies, choices, ecosystems – and from within the human mind itself.

All these perplexing complexities rush along and seek to convince us that the world is like a runaway roller-coaster, rocking and rolling; that everything we once held to be true might one day be overthrown. Some even see such a prospect as a reason to be suspicious of science3 as a corrosive effect upon the foundations of human nature and certainty, as though the construction of the physical Universe and the vast schema of its laws should have been set up with our psychological fragility in mind.

But there is a sense in which all this change and unpredictability is an illusion. It is not the whole story about the nature of the Universe. There is both a conservative and a progressive side to the deep structure of reality. Despite the incessant change and dynamic of the visible world, there are aspects of the fabric of the Universe which are mysterious in their unshakeable constancy. It is these mysterious unchanging things that make our Universe what it is and distinguish it from other worlds that we might imagine. There is a golden thread that weaves a continuity through Nature. It leads us to expect that certain things elsewhere in space will be the same as they are here on Earth; that they were and will be the same at other times as they are today; that for some things neither history nor geography matter. Indeed, perhaps without such a substratum of unchanging realities there could be no surface currents of change or any complexities of mind and matter at all.

These bedrock ingredients of our Universe are what this book is about. Their existence is one of the last mysteries of science that has challenged a succession of great physicists to come up with an explanation for why they are as they are. Our quest is to discover what they are but we have long known only what to call them. They are the constants of Nature. They lie at the root of sameliness in the Universe: why every electron seems to be the same as every other electron.

The constants of Nature encode the deepest secrets of the Universe. They express at once our greatest knowledge and our greatest ignorance about the cosmos. Their existence has taught us the profound truth that Nature abounds with unseen regularities. Yet, while we have become skilled at measuring the values of these constant quantities, our inability to explain or predict their values shows how much we have still to learn about the inner workings of the Universe.

What is the ultimate status of the constants of Nature? Are they truly constant? Are they everywhere the same? Are they all linked? Could life have evolved and persisted if they were even slightly different? These are some of the issues that this book will grapple with. It will look back to the discoveries of the first constants of Nature and the impact they had on scientists and theologians looking for Mind, purpose and design in Nature. It will show what frontier science now believes constants of Nature to be and whether a future Theory of Everything, if it exists, will one day reveal the true secret of the constants of Nature. And most important of all, it will ask whether they are truly constant.

chapter two

Journey Towards Ultimate Reality

Franklin: Have you ever thought, Headmaster, that your standards might perhaps be a little out of date?

Headmaster: Of course they’re out of date. Standards always are out of date. That is what makes them standards.’

Alan Bennett1

MISSION TO MARS

‘The Mars Climate Orbiter Mishap Investigation Board has determined that the root cause for the loss of the Mars Climate Orbiter spacecraft was the failure to use metric units.’

NASA Mars Climate Orbiter Mishap Investigation Report2

IN THE LAST week of September 1998 NASA was getting ready to hit the press agencies with a big story. The Mars Climate Explorer, designed to skim through the upper atmosphere of Mars, was about to send back important data about the Martian atmosphere and climate. Instead, it just crashed into the Martian surface. In NASAs words,

‘The MCO spacecraft, designed to study the weather and climate of Mars, was launched by a Delta rocket on December 11th, 1998, from Cape Canaveral Air Station, Florida. After a cruise to Mars of approximately 9½ months, the spacecraft fired its main engine to go into orbit around Mars at around 2 a.m. PDT on September 23, 1999. Five minutes into the planned 16-minute burn, the spacecraft passed behind the planet as seen from Earth. Signal reacquisition, nominally expected at approximately 2:26 a.m. PDT did not occur. Efforts to find and communicate with MCO continued up until 3 p.m. PDT on September 24, 1999, when they were abandoned.’3

The spacecraft was 60 miles (96.6 km) closer to the Martian surface than the mission controllers thought, and $125 million disappeared into the red Martian dust. The loss was bad enough but when the cause was discovered it looked like a case for the force-feeding of humble pie. Lockheed-Martin, the company controlling the day-to-day operation of the spacecraft, was sending out data about the thrusters in Imperial units, miles, feet and pounds-force, to mission control, while NASA’s navigation team was assuming like the rest of the international scientific world that they were receiving their instructions in metric units. The difference between miles and kilometres was enough to send the craft 60 miles off course on a suicidal orbit into the Martian surface.4

The lesson of this débâcle is clear. Units matter. Our predecessors have bequeathed us countless everyday units of measurement that we tend to use in different situations for the sake of convenience. We buy eggs in dozens, bid at auctions in guineas, measure horse races in furlongs, ocean depths in fathoms, apples in bushels, coal in hundredweight, lifetimes in years and weigh gemstones in carats. Accounts of all the standards of measurement in past and present existence run to hundreds of pages. All this was entirely satisfactory while commerce was local and simple. But as communities started to trade internationally in ancient times they started to encounter other ways of counting. Quantity was measured differently from country to country and conversion factors were needed, just as we change currency when travelling internationally today. Once international collaboration began on technical projects the stakes were raised.5 Precision engineering requires accurate inter-comparison of standards. It is all very well telling your collaborators on the other side of the world that they need to make an aircraft component that is precisely one metre long, but how do you know that their metre is the same as your metre?

MEASURE FOR MEASURE – PAROCHIAL STANDARDS

‘She does not understand the concept of Roman numerals.

She thought we just fought World War Eleven.’

Joan Rivers6

Originally, standards of measurement were entirely parochial and anthropometric. Lengths were derived from the length of the king’s arm or the span of his hand. Distances mirrored the extent of a day’s journey. Time followed the astronomical variations of the Earth and Moon. Weights were convenient quantities that could be carried in the hand or on the back. Many of these measures were wisely chosen and are still with us today in spite of the official ubiquity of the decimal system. None is sacrosanct. Each is designed for convenience in particular circumstances. Many measures of distance were derived anthropomorphically from the dimensions of human anatomy. The ‘foot’ is the most obvious unit of this sort. Others are no longer so familiar. The ‘yard’ was the length of a tape drawn from the tip of a man’s nose to the farthest fingertip of his arm when stretched horizontally to one side. The ‘cubit’ was the distance from a man’s elbow joint to furthermost fingertip of his outstretched hand, and varies between about 17 and 25 of our inches (0.44–0.64 metres) in the different ancient cultures that employed it.7 The nautical unit of length, the fathom, was the largest distance-unit defined from the human anatomy, and was defined as the maximum distance between the fingertips of a man with both hands outstretched horizontally to the side.

The movement of merchants and traders around the Mediterranean region in ancient times would have highlighted the different measures of the same anatomical distance. This would have made it difficult to maintain any single set of units. But national tradition and habit was a powerful force in resisting the adoption of another country’s standards.

The most obvious problem with such units is the fact that men and women come in different sizes. Who do you measure as your standard? The king or queen is the obvious candidate. Even so, this results in a recalibration of units every time the throne changes hands. One notable response to the problem of the variation in human dimensions was that devised by David I of Scotland in 1150 to define the Scottish inch: he ordained that it was to be the average drawn from measurements of the width of the base of the thumbnail of three men: a ‘mekill’ [big] man, a man of ‘messurabel’ [moderate] stature, and a ‘lytell’ [little] man.

The modern metric system of centimetres, kilograms and litres, and the traditional ‘Imperial’ system of inches, pounds and pints are equally good measures of lengths, weights and volumes so long as you can measure them accurately. That is not the same thing as saying they are equally convenient, though. The metric system mirrors our counting system by having each unit ten times bigger than the next smallest. Imagine having a counting system that had uneven jumps. So, instead of hundreds, tens and units we had a counting system like that used in England for non-technical weights (like human body weights or horse-racing handicaps) with 16 ounces in one pound and 14 pounds in one stone.

The cleaning up of standards of measurement began decisively at the time of the French Revolution at the end of the eighteenth century. Introducing new weights and measures brings with it a certain upheaval in society and is rarely received with unalloyed enthusiasm by the populace. The French Revolution therefore provided an occasion to make such an innovation without adding significantly to the general upheaval of everything else.8 The prevailing trend of political thinking at the time sided with the view that weights and measures should have an egalitarian standard that did not make them the property of any one nation, nor give any nation an advantage when it came to trading with others. The way to do this was believed to define measure against some agreed standard, from which all rulers and secondary measures would be calibrated. The French National Assembly enacted this into law on 26 March 1791, with the support of Louis XVI and the clear statement of principle submitted by Charles Maurice de Talleyrand:

‘In view of the fact that in order to be able to introduce uniformity of weights and measures it is necessary that a natural and unchanging unit of mass be laid down, and that the only means of extending this uniformity to other nations and urging them to agree upon a system of measures is to choose a unit that is not arbitrary and does not contain anything specific to any peoples on the globe.’9

Two years later, the ‘metre’10 was introduced as the standard of length, defined as the ten millionth part of a quarter of the Earth’s meridian.11 Although this is a plausible way to identify a standard of length it is clearly not very practical as an everyday comparison. Consequently, in 1795, the units were directly related to specially made objects. At first the unit of mass was taken as the gram, defined to be the mass of one cubic centimetre of water at 0 degrees centigrade. Later it was superseded by the kilogram (1000 grams) defined as the mass of 1000 cubic centimetres of water at 4 degrees centigrade. Finally, in 1799, a prototype metre bar12 was made together with a standard kilogram mass and placed in the archives of the new French Republic. Even today, the reference kilogram mass is known as the ‘Kilogramme des Archives’.

Unfortunately, the new metric units were not at first successful and Napoleon reintroduced the old standards in the early years of the nineteenth century. The European political situation prevented an international harmonisation of standards.13 It was not until New Year’s Day 1840 that Louis Phillipe made metric units legally obligatory in France. Meanwhile they had already been adopted more universally in the Netherlands, Belgium and Luxembourg twenty-four years earlier, and by Greece in 1832. Britain only allowed a rather restricted use of metric units after 1864 and the USA followed suit two years later. Real progress only occurred in 1870 when the International Metre Commission was established and met in Paris on 8 August for the first time, to coordinate standards and oversee the making of new standard masses and lengths.14 Copies of the standards were distributed to some of the member states chosen by the drawing of lots. The kilogram was the mass of a special cylinder, 39 mm in height and diameter, made of an alloy of platinum and iridium15 kept under three glass bell-jars and stored inside a vault at the International Bureau of Standards in Sèvres near Paris. Its definition is simple:16

‘The kilogram is the unit of mass; it is equal to the mass of the international prototype of the kilogram.’

The British Imperial units, like the yard and the pound, were defined similarly and standard prototypes were kept by the National Physical Laboratory in England and the National Bureau of Standards in Washington DC.

This trend for standardisation saw the creation of scientific units of measurement. As a result we habitually measure lengths, masses and times in multiples of metres, kilograms and seconds. One unit of each gives a familiar quantity that is easily imagined: a metre of cloth, a kilogram of potatoes. This convenience of size witnesses at once to their anthropocentric pedigree. But its inconvenience also becomes obvious when we start to use these units to describe quantities that are super- or sub-human in scale. The smallest atoms are 10 billion times smaller than a metre. The Sun is more than 1030 kilograms in mass. In Figure 2.1 we show the span of sizes and masses of significant objects in the Universe with ourselves added for perspective. We sit in between the huge astronomical distances and masses and the sub-atomic scale of the most elementary particles of matter.

The mass and

Figure 2.1 The mass and size ranges of some important ingredients of the Universe. Our choice of centimetres and grams as units places us close to the centre of things.

Despite the introduction of universal metric standards by international commissions and government ministers, the ordinary worker took little notice of edicts about units, especially in Britain where a huge multiplicity of special units were in play throughout every branch of industry and commerce. By the middle of the nineteenth century, the industrial revolution had created diverse human sub-cultures of engineers and brewers, accountants and metalworkers, timekeepers and ship workers, all of whom needed ways of measuring the materials that they managed and manipulated. The result was an explosion of units of measure. Every type of material began to have its own standard of strength and tolerance, quantity and weight. Not only were these units anthropocentric they were profession-centric as well. Brewers liked one choice of volume measure, water engineers another; jewellers measured weight differently to sailors and architects. When I was a child there was a common brand of lined exercise book that would be used for making notes at school. They always had red or blue covers and the outside back cover of the book listed all the peculiar Imperial measures of length, area, capacity and weight (see Figure 2.2).

A typical set

Figure 2.2 A typical set of miscellaneous weights and measures from an English self-help book of the 1950s.17

For the engineer and the practical person of affairs this was convenient, useful and no doubt very profitable. But for anyone seeking an integrated natural philosophy it made human knowledge appear fragmented and idiosyncratic. A visitor from another planet would be perplexed by the need for different measures of weight when buying gold, apples or sealing wax.

MAINTAINING UNIVERSAL STANDARDS

‘There was a crooked man who built a crooked house.’

Nursery rhyme

By the second half of the nineteenth century, engineers, industrialists and scientists were becoming overwhelmed by the profusion of ad hoc units and measures. The industrial revolution had accelerated the development of every imaginable industry. Manufacturing, machining, measuring, designing, building – these were the rages of the age and they spawned more and more units.

Within the halls of science the existence of standard lengths and masses was not entirely satisfactory for the purist either. Every time standard masses were handled with their special tongs their mass would be very slightly changed. It would vary slightly as atoms were evaporated from their surfaces or dust deposited from the atmosphere. They were not really constant.18 Nor were they universal. Suppose that a signal had been received from an engineer on another planet asking us how big we were. It would be no use sending an answer in metres or kilograms and then responding to the inevitable reply, ‘What are they?’ by telling our extraterrestrial correspondent that they were objects kept in glass containers in Paris. Unfortunately the quest for universal standards had created examples which were neither standard nor universal.

Within science the driving force for rationalisation came from the study of electricity and magnetism. Different systems of units were in use by different groups of scientists and had different relationships with the traditional metric units for mass, length, time and temperature.

The first general response to these problems came from Lord Rayleigh and James Clerk Maxwell. In his Presidential address to the British Association for the Advancement of Science in 1870 Maxwell advocated the introduction of standards which are not tied to special objects, like standard metres19 or kilograms kept in special conditions. For standards like these can never really be constant. The standard mass in Paris will lose and gain molecules all the time. Measures of time that are defined, like the day, by the rotation of the Earth or, like the year, by its orbit of the Sun likewise cannot be constant. As the rotation of the Earth slows, and our solar circuit changes, so these standards will very slowly drift. They may be defined in extrahuman terms but they are not candidates for ultimate standards. Maxwell had spent a good deal of time studying the behaviour of molecules in gases and was very impressed by the way in which each molecule of hydrogen was the same as all the others. This was quite different to dealing with large, everyday objects where every one was different. Maxwell saw an opportunity to use the sameness of molecules to define standards absolutely:

‘Yet, after all, the dimensions of our earth and its time of rotation, though, relatively to our present means of comparison, very permanent, are not so by any physical necessity. The earth might contract by cooling, or it might be enlarged by a layer of meteorites falling on it, or its rate of revolution might slowly slacken, and yet it would continue to be as much a planet as before.

But a molecule, say of hydrogen, if either its mass or its time of vibration were to be altered in the least, would no longer be a molecule of hydrogen.

If, then, we wish to obtain standards of length, time, and mass which shall be absolutely permanent, we must seek them not in the dimensions, or the motion, or the mass of our planet, but in the wave-length, the period of vibration, and the absolute mass of these imperishable and unalterable and perfectly similar molecules [i.e. atoms].20

Maxwell was specially interested in molecules for many philosophical purposes. He recognised the significance of there existing populations of identical building blocks for all the material bodies we see around us. If we take any piece of pure iron it will be composed of a collection of identical iron molecules. The fact that these molecules appear to be identical is a remarkable feature of the world. Maxwell contrasted this invariance with the changeability and evolution of living things predicted by Charles Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection. Maxwell pointed to the molecules of Nature as entities that were not subject to selection, adaptation or mutation. His challenge was to find a way to exploit this immutability and universality in the way that we define our units of measurement. In this way we would be able to take a step away from the bias introduced by the imperatives of human convenience towards the deep invariances of physical reality.

In 1905 the red light emitted by hot cadmium atoms21 was first used as a standard against which to define a unit of length called the Angstrom (denoted by 1Å and equal to 10−10 metre). One wavelength of the cadmium light was equal to 6438.4696 Å. This was a key step because for the first time it defined a standard of length in terms of a universally constant feature of Nature. The wavelength of the light emitted by cadmium22 is fixed by the constants of Nature alone. If we wanted to tell an extraterrestrial physicist our size, we could do it by saying what we mean by 2.8 billion wavelengths of red cadmium light.23

A BRILLIANT IDEA!

‘“Where did the matter come from?”

“What is the difference? … The secret of the universe is apathy. The earth, the sun, the rocks, they’re all indifferent, and this is a kind of passive force. Perhaps indifference and gravitation are the same.”’

Isaac Bashevis Singer24

In 1874, an unusual Irish physicist called George Johnstone Stoney found himself having to make sense of the Babel of practical units. He had been invited to deliver a lecture on units of measurement at the annual meeting of the British Association for the Advancement of Science in Belfast.25 This annual meeting still exists today but is now devoted to showcasing the developments in science for the general public, the Press and young people. But in Stoney’s day it was the foremost science conference in the world, a place where great discoveries would be made public and the Press would report on great debates between leading scientists and commentators. Today there are so many specialised scientific conferences, workshops, meetings, discussions, panel discussions and round tables that there is no longer any place for a meeting that covers all of science at a technical level – it would be impossibly big, impossibly lengthy, and well nigh unintelligible to most of the participants much of the time.

Stoney was an eccentric and original thinker. He was the first person to show how to deduce whether or not other planets in the solar system possessed a gaseous atmosphere, like the Earth, by calculating whether their surface gravity was strong enough to hold on to one. But his real passion was reserved for his most treasured idea – the ‘electron’. Stoney had deduced that there must exist a basic ingredient of electric charge. By studying Michael Faraday’s experiments on electrolysis Stoney had even predicted27 what its value must be – a prediction subsequently confirmed by J.J. Thomson who discovered the electron in Cambridge in 189728 and announced his discovery to the Royal Institution on 30 April. To this basic quota of electric charge Stoney eventually gave the name ‘electron’ and the symbol E in 189129 (after first calling it30 the ‘electrine’ in 1874) and he never missed an opportunity to publicise its properties and potential benefits for science.31

The Irish

Figure 2.3 The Irish physicist George Johnstone Stoney (1826–1911).26

Stoney was also an older distant cousin of the famous mathematician, computer scientist and code-breaker, Alan Turing, whose mother recalled childhood memories of the unusual uncle the children called ‘electron Stoney’.32 He was also the uncle of George FitzGerald, now famous for proposing the Lorentz-FitzGerald contraction of length, a phenomenon that was eventually understood within the context of Einstein’s special theory of relativity. Stoney was also a practical man and worked for two years for the Earl of Rosse constructing sensitive optical instruments for his private observatory at Birr Castle before becoming Professor of Natural Philosophy at Queen’s College Galway in 1850. After his retirement he moved to Hornsey in north London and continued publishing a steady stream of papers in the Royal Dublin Society’s scientific journal. It is hard to find an issue that doesn’t contain a paper under his name, on every conceivable subject, we find everything from time travel to how bicycles stay upright.

Stoney found the programme for the Belfast meeting of the British Association full of accounts of different units and standards: how to measure them; how best to define them; how to inter-relate them. This was all very useful for insiders but somewhat tedious for everyone else. Stoney saw an opportunity to simplify this vast perplexity of human standards of measurement and to do so in a way that would lend more weight to his electron hypothesis. Stoney had been a member of a British Association committee33 which had determined conventions for electrical units in the years leading up to this conference, and so had already been required to give some thought to the problems of units and standards.

Stoney recognised that his concept of the basic electronic charge unit provided the missing piece in a small puzzle. Suppose that one wanted to devise units of mass, length and time that were not attached to purely human standards of convenience, like the pound or the mile or the fortnight. Then they needed to be derived from some aspect of the underlying fabric of the Universe that was not anthropocentric, that did not depend on where you are located when you measure it, or when the measurement was made. This ruled out traditional approaches to standards which took a standard mass of a kilogram or a length of a metre and kept them in a specially controlled environment somewhere and just compared other reference masses or lengths to them. These masses and lengths are anthropocentric in origin but, what is worse, they are anthropocentric in principle because there is no way in which to tell extraterrestrials how much mass or length defines our standard without sending it to them.

In order to escape the shackles of anthropocentric bias Stoney looked to the constants of physics to supply something that might transcend human standards of quantity. Newton had discovered that gravity obeys an apparently universal law. The force between two masses whose centres are separated by a distance is proportional to each of their masses and inversely proportional to the square of the distance between their centres. The constant of proportionality should be the same everywhere in the universe.34 This constant, G, gives a measure of the strength of gravity. The important thing about it is that it is believed to be constant35 – the same value should be found everywhere it is correctly measured. Moreover, it has a strange value when expressed in our convenient anthropocentric units (G = 6.67259 × 10−11 m3s−2kg−1) because those units were devised for other anthropocentric purposes.

The second constant of Nature that Stoney appealed to for his non-anthropocentric standards was the speed of light, c. Again, this quantity transcends human standards. It has a fundamental significance. In fact, it has an even more fundamental significance than Stoney could ever have known. Einstein showed that the speed of light in a vacuum should act as the ultimate speed limit in the Universe – no information can be sent faster. It had also been discovered that the product of the permeability and permittivity of space that defined different units of electricity was equal to the square of the speed of light, so revealing its special universal status with respect to electricity as well. To these two constant quantities Stoney added his own candidate for the third great constant of Nature – his basic electron charge, which we now label by the symbol e. It was the last piece needed to complete the jigsaw. It fitted the bill in the same way as G and c. It was presumed to be universal. It was associated with a fundamental aspect of the structure of Nature. And it didn’t care about human convenience. Stoney announced his trinity of constants like this:36

‘Nature presents us with three such units and that if we take these as our fundamental units, instead of choosing them arbitrarily, we shall bring our quantitative expressions into a more convenient, and doubtless into a more intimate, relation with Nature as it actually exists.

For such a purpose we must select phenomena that prevail throughout the whole of Nature, and are not simply associated with individual bodies. The first of Nature’s quantities of absolute magnitude to which I will invite attention is that remarkable velocity of an absolute amount, independent of the units in which it is measured, which connects all systematic electrostatic units with the electromagnetic units of the same series. I shall call this velocity V1 [i.e. our c]. If it were taken as our unit velocity we should at one stroke have an immense simplification introduced into our treatment of the whole range of electric phenomena, and probably into our study of light and heat.

Again Nature presents us with one particular coefficient of gravitation, of an absolute amount independent of the units in which it is measured, and which appears to extend to ponderable matter of every description throughout the whole material universe. This coefficient I shall call G1 [i.e. our G]. If we were to take this as our unit of coefficients of attraction, it is presumable that we might thereby lay the foundation for detecting wherein lies the connection which we cannot but suspect between this most wonderful property common to all ponderable matter, and the other phenomena of nature.

And, finally, Nature presents us in the phenomenon of electrolysis, with a single definite quantity of electricity which is independent of the particular bodies acted on … This definite quantity of electricity I shall call E1 [i.e. our e]. If we make this our unit quantity of electricity, we shall probably have made a very important step in our study of molecular phenomena.

Hence we have very good reason to suppose that in V1, G1, and E1 [i.e. c, G and e] we have three of a series of systematic units that in an eminent sense are the units of Nature, and stand in an intimate relation with the work which goes on in her mighty laboratory.

We have thus obtained … the three great fundamental units offered to us by Nature, upon which may be built an entire series of physical units deserving of the title of a truly Natural Series of Physical Units.’

In his talk Stoney referred to the electron as the ‘electrine’ and gave the first calculation of its expected value.37 He showed that the magic trio of G, c and e could be combined in one way, and only one way, so that a unit of mass, a unit of length and a unit of time are created from them. For the velocity of light he used an average of existing measurements, c = 3 × 108 metres per second; for Newton’s gravitation constant he used the value obtained by John Herschel, G = 0.67 × 10−11 m3 Kg−1s−2, and for his unit of ‘electrine’ charge he used e = 10−20 Ampères.38 Here are the unusual new units that he found, in terms of the constants e, c and G, and in terms of grams, metres and seconds:

MJ = (e2/G)1/2 = 10−7 gram

LJ = (Ge2/c4)1/2 = 10−37 metres

TJ = (Ge2/c6)1/2 = 3 × 10−46 seconds

These are extraordinary quantities. Although a mass of 10−7 gram is not too outlandish, similar to that of a speck of dust, Stoney’s units of length and time were unlike any that had been encountered by scientists before. They were fantastically, almost inconceivably, small. There was (and still is) no possibility of measuring such lengths and times directly. In a way, that is what one might have expected. These units are deliberately not constructed from human dimensions, for human convenience, or for human utility. They are defined by the very fabric of physical reality that determines the nature of light, electricity and gravity. They don’t care about us.

Stoney had succeeded brilliantly in his quest for a superhuman system of units. But, alas, they attracted little attention. There was no practical use for his ‘natural’ units and their significance was hidden to everyone, even Stoney himself, who was more interested in promoting his electron up until its discovery in 1897. Natural units needed to be discovered all over again.

MAX PLANCK’S NATURAL UNITS

‘Science cannot solve the ultimate mystery of nature. And that is because, in the last analysis, we ourselves are part of the mystery that we are trying to solve.’

Max Planck39

Stoney’s idea was rediscovered in a slightly different form by the German physicist Max Planck, in 1899. Planck is one of the most important physicists of all time. He discovered the quantum nature of energy that launched the quantum revolution in our understanding of the world and provided the first correct description of heat radiation (the so called ‘Planck spectrum’) and has one of the fundamental constants of Nature named after him. He was a central figure in physics of his time, won the Nobel prize for physics in 1918, and died in 1947 aged 89. A quiet, unassuming man, he was deeply religious40 and greatly admired by his younger contemporaries, like Einstein and Bohr.

Planck’s conception of Nature placed great emphasis upon its intrinsic rationality and independence of human thought. He believed in an intelligence behind the appearances which fixed the nature of reality. Our most fundamental conceptions of Nature needed to be aware of the need to identify that deep structure which was far from the needs of human utility and convenience. In the last year of his life he was asked by a former student if he believed that the quest to unite all the constants of Nature by some deeper theory was appealing. He replied with enthusiasm, tempered by realism about the difficulty of the challenge:

‘As to your question about the connections between the universal constants, it is without doubt an attractive idea to link them together as closely as possible by reducing these various constants to a single one. I for my part, however, am doubtful that this will be successful. But I may be mistaken.’41

Unlike Einstein, Planck did not really believe in any attainable all-encompassing theory of physics which would explain all the constants of Nature. For if such a theory arrived then physics would cease to be an inductive science. Others, like Pierre Duhem and Percy Bridgman, regarded the promised Planckian separation of scientific description from human conventions as unattainable in principle, viewing the constants of Nature and the theoretical descriptions that they underpin entirely as artefacts of a particular human choice of representation to make sense of what was seen.

Planck was suspicious of attributing fundamental significance to quantities that had been created as a result of the ‘accident’ of our situation:

‘All the systems of units that have hitherto been employed, including the so-called absolute C. G. S. system [centimetre, gram and second, for measuring length, mass and time], owe their origin to the coincidence of accidental circumstances, inasmuch as the choice of the units lying at the base of every system has been made, not according to general points of view which would necessarily retain their importance for all places and all times, but essentially with reference to the special needs of our terrestrial civilization …

Thus the units of length and time were derived from the present dimensions and motion of our planet, and the units of mass temperature from the density and the most important temperature points of water, as being the liquid which plays the most important part on the surface of the earth, under a pressure which corresponds to the mean properties of the atmosphere surrounding us. It would be no less arbitrary if, let us say, the invariable wave length of Na-light were taken as unit of length. For, again, the particular choice of Na from among the many chemical elements could be justified only, perhaps, by its common occurrence on the earth, or by its double line, which is in the range of our vision, but is by no means the only one of its kind. Hence it is quite conceivable that at some other time, under changed external conditions, every one of the systems of units which have so far been adopted for use might lose, in part or wholly, its original natural significance.’

Instead, he wanted to see the establishment of

‘units of length, mass, time and temperature which are independent of special bodies or substances, which necessarily retain their significance for all times and for all environments, terrestrial and human or otherwise’.42

Whereas Stoney had seen a way of cutting the Gordian knot of subjectivity in the choice of practical units, Planck used his special units to underpin a non-anthropomorphic basis for physics and ‘which may, therefore, be described as “natural units”.’ The progressive revelation of this basis was for him the hallmark of real progress towards as far-reaching a separation as possible of the phenomena in the external world from those in human consciousness.

In accord with his universal outlook, in 1899 Planck proposed43 that natural units of mass, length and time be constructed from the most fundamental constants of Nature: the gravitation constant G, the speed of light c, and the constant of action, h, which now bears Planck’s name.44 Planck’s constant determines the smallest amount by which energy can be changed (the ‘quantum’). In addition, the incorporation of Boltzmann’s constant, k − which simply converts units of energy into units of temperature – allowed him also to define a natural temperature.45 Planck’s units are the only combinations of these constants which can be formed with the dimensions of mass, length, time and temperature. Their values are not very different from Stoney’s:

mpl = (hc/G)1/2 = 5.56 × 10−5 gram

lpl = (Gh/c3)1/2 = 4.13 × 10−33 centimetres

tpl = (Gh/c5)1/2−43